The BOOKPRESS | May 1999 |
Later, upon my appointment
to the Faculty Committee on Student Affairs, I was a participant in the
long and exhausting hours spent by the committee in trying to come to terms
with the refusal of those blacks to acquiesce in any judgment upon their
actions made in accordance with a code that to them was designed by whites
in a university they accused of "institutional racial bias." Downs remarks,
quite correctly, that the judicial code was based on the assumption that
individuals are responsible for their actions, while the more militant
members of the Afro-American Society were engaged in the politics of group
identity and recognition.
Anybody’s memory of
disturbing events thirty years in the past may be colored by later memories
or by an attempt at self-justification. With as much objectivity as I’m
capable of giving my earlier self, I can say that the response of the black
students at my door, which to me acknowledged their respect for teaching,
had something to do with my unsuccessful attempt to get the FCSA to dismiss
the charges against them. I considered their actions to have taken on a
symbolic import—simply because they were black—far beyond the trivial damage
they were accused of. I was comparing the "spree" to the disturbances of
past Dragon Days, when architecture students marched through Goldwin Smith,
even entering classes to spew green-dyed liquids on professors unwary enough
to leave their doors unlocked—a disruptive event, surely, but one that
aroused no furor. Unlike such disruptions, this one had a calculated political
motive; I was naive in assuming that dropping the charges would resolve
anything. My committee’s refusal to drop them brought the takeover of Willard
Straight Hall and the alarming introduction of weapons. But after the faculty
itself nullified even more than the original charges, the black leadership
was not content, refusing even to participate in a revision of the code
they had objected to. They wanted an educational autonomy that disregarded
not only state law but the Supreme Court ruling that made the doctrine
of "separate but equal" a violation of Constitutional intent.
The compromise ultimately
decided upon—an early form of the present program in Africana Studies—resulted
in an absence of black students in most of the classes I taught in the
following decades. In the pre-1969 years, this was not the case; some of
the later black leaders were students of mine as well as of the faculty
mentioned by Downs who supported academic freedom above all else. Today,
I find it surprising—given all that was waiting to occur—to recall that
once I accused Tom Jones, who became perhaps the most incendiary black
leader, of using both his undeniable charm and the color of his skin to
avoid dedicating himself enough to the work of my class. If my memory is
correct, he accepted my accusation, but with a justification that would
cheer the heart of conservatives today who decry affirmative action: the
university itself had influenced him to be that way, for the color of his
skin and not any financial need (his parents being well-off) had provided
him with financial benefits and other dispensations.
Another black mentioned
in the book was one with whom I felt a particular spiritual and intellectual
affinity. Not only were his insights into the literature the class was
reading unusually insightful—actually, I learned from them—but both of
us were persuaded by Camus’ distinction between resentment and rebellion.
(To Camus, resentment is an impotent envy for what one does not have or
is not, while rebellion comes from an implicit assumption of equality with
others: the rebel demands recognition of what he is, what he shares with
them.) Still another black student would smile, wave her hands, and shout
at me halfway across the whole Arts Quad, "Hello, Professor McConkey"—always
a warning, for whenever it happened the AAS was planning some strategy
to make even more difficult the decisions facing the committee of which
she knew I was a member.
"The Cornell story,"
Downs tell us early on, "is about the failure of liberalism to protect
intellectual freedom in the face of imperative social justice claims, thereby
providing a blueprint for the severing of these principles that compromises
higher education to this day." His greatest criticism is directed against
President James Perkins for a liberal political bias at the expense of
academic freedom—a bias that caused him to lose control; but Downs also
condemns the faculty, particularly those who let their own desire for political
justice in America take such precedence over academic freedom that they
not only sympathized with Perkins but failed to support any corrective
action themselves. (I think none of us, including those supporters of academic
freedom who despised him, came as we should have to Perkins’ defense, on
those occasions when he—who represented by virtue of his office the university
itself—was humiliated or threatened.)
Near the end of his
book, in discussing the "Barton Hall Community," Downs seems to be implying
what those compromises in higher education today consist of: in his view,
that assemblage of students and a scattering of faculty members "signified
the beginning of the ‘political correctness’ that took off in the 1980s,
when the activists of the 1960s—the heirs of Perkins—began to hold positions
of power in universities." (To me, that "Community" was remarkably hopeful,
receptive to all possible ideas perhaps because activists did not interfere.)
His judgment here—simplistic for many reasons —is similar to that of many
political conservatives, whose own righteousness is another, if related,
subject; but the righteousness that then afflicted groups on the right
as well as the left (and many individuals, though not to my knowledge Perkins
himself) suggests the real difficulty in times of crisis of distinguishing
between intellectual freedom and ideology.
Downs’ thesis, augmented
as it is by those on the faculty he chose to interview, makes his judgment
of Perkins too harsh for a tragic figure enmeshed within his own good intentions.
Downs is unfair in contrasting Perkins to Robert Hutchins of the University
of Chicago, who believed, in Downs’ paraphrase, "that the university can
serve society only if it does not surrender its distinctive meaning and
form to external forces." Hutchins, that proponent of Great Books and humanistic
education, had the good fortune throughout his long career as university
president and chancellor to exist in an America still confident in its
own virtue and its role as inheritor of the Greek gift of democracy—though,
ironically, Athenian democracy was limited to male citizens, its repose
for philosophical inquiry dependent upon slavery. Hutchins never had to
withstand the outer assaults and inner pressures, the growing sense of
moral outrage, occasioned by the Vietnam War, that brought about a widespread
disobedience (justified by the Nuremberg trials) to legislation and procedures
considered unjust. The growing discontent toppled not only the president
of Cornell but the President of the United States, undoing in the process
Lyndon Johnson’s War on Poverty—much of it aimed, like Perkins’ more circumscribed
efforts, at helping blacks overcome the discrimination they had been historically
accorded.
Minor player though
I was in the Cornell events of 1969, I was exhausted almost to the point
of spiritual paralysis, and was glad to take a sabbatical leave. In Italy
the following year, I wrote a novel I didn’t really want to write, a fictionalized
account of the events I’d just lived through. Once I got started, I found
myself writing more easily than I ever had, but without any sense of my
conclusion. Every day, as I finished, I had a clear idea of no more than
what I would write the following day. Only when I was at the end, and had
killed off my protagonist, did I realize that I had just destroyed what
I had come to disdain in myself—a posture of compromise based on the wish
to be liked. Unconsciously I had felt the need to destroy that self, in
order to construct a social identity I could better live with, one that
could resist the blandishments of any peer group.
In experiencing that
year at Cornell, but even more so in writing about it, I was aware of scheming
on the part of a few blacks—the kind of behavior we refer to as machiavellian.
But that they (or white activists, for that matter) would actually attempt
to demoralize and divide a university by acts consciously intended not
only to intimidate but to encourage white guilt while inciting racial hatred
(the most obvious of the examples being their own burning of a cross before
the residence of black women)—this struck me as so contemptible, so morally
indefensible, that at the time I could not even imagine it, whatever the
growing evidence. I find it likely that Perkins couldn’t imagine it, at
least soon enough, either—though, on the basis of Downs’ book, it seems
that some of the staunchest defenders of intellectual freedom could. Had
Perkins been able to imagine it for the devious revolutionary strategy
it was (or turned out to be: activists can increasingly get caught up in
their own early rhetoric), he could have taken a firmer position capable
of giving direction to ensuing policies. So even in our innocence, we humans
can be judged guilty.
This may be as sound
a conclusion as I can make, but I am not satisfied with it.
Democracy, like the
freedom of intellectual expression that stems from it, is a concept as
precious as it is fragile. Freedom of intellectual expression is a "good,"
but why is it so? Because it is the freedom to search for truth. In science,
truth can be objective, made verifiable by factual evidence; but humanistic
truth, whatever the factual buttressing, remains as subjective as the values
through which we daily interpret the reality in which we live, and can
limit or broaden the pursuit of even the purest of academic ideals. For
reasons whose seed, if it is to be located at all, goes back at least a
century and a half ago (some carry it much farther back) subjective truth
has become a series of relative and seemingly disparate and frequently
conflicting truths which in unstable times give ideologues an easy entrance.
It is clear (at least
to me) that none of these fragmented truths—busily though each may be taught
today, each important in itself—has any real meaning unless all are brought
together under a truth large enough to encompass them all, and in so doing
reflect our common human origin and fate. Without such spiritual insight,
and the social reforms that can stem from it, we may be destined—particularly
if the present boom turns to bust—to further separation and resentment
in America, to a self-hatred expressed by hatred for others capable once
again of eroding academic freedom, even if genetic cloning could resurrect
enough copies of Robert Hutchins to preside over every one of our universities;
with it, we can rebel against injustice while remaining part of the single
human race each of us undeniably represents.
Cornell ’69
is a gripping, a necessary, cautionary tale; my reservations are no dismissal
of its message.
James McConkey
is a writer and the fiction editor of The Bookpress.
Though the severe
racial disturbances that are the subject of Cornell ’69: Liberalism
and the Crisis of the American University continued into the next year,
Downs’ book focuses on the period of my own involvement in the central
judicial questions. The crisis over judicial processes was foreshadowed,
as Downs in his careful analysis points out, by earlier events; but the
particular event that led to the black takeover of Willard Straight Hall
and then to the downfall of the judicial system was what he refers to as
a "toy gun spree." Seven black students stopped traffic and disrupted activities
in a couple of buildings; in a third, Goldwin Smith Hall, "they overturned
two candy machines, discharged a fire extinguisher, and ran down the hallways
banging on doors of offices and classrooms." It so happened that I was
leading a seminar of maybe five undergraduates in my basement office across
from the Temple of Zeus when they knocked upon and then opened the door:
"Oh, there’s a class going on," one of them said, and quietly closed the
door. We then heard the crash as they toppled a candy machine at the end
of the corridor.
Return to Front Page |